Capitalism & Competition 1.O
INTRODUCTION
Capitalism is an economic system based on
the private ownership of the means of production and their operation for 1
profit. Central characteristics of capitalism include capital accumulation,
competitive markets, a price system, private property and the recognition of
property rights, voluntary exchange and wage labor. In a capitalist market
economy, decision-making and investments are determined by owners of wealth,
property, or production ability in capital and financial markets-whereas prices
and the distribution of goods and services are mainly determined by competition
in goods and services markets.
Economists, historians, political
economists and sociologists have adopted different perspectives in their
analyses of capitalism and have recognized various forms of it in practice.
These include laissez-faire or free market capitalism, state capitalism and
welfare capitalism. Different forms of capitalism feature varying degrees of
free markets, public ownership, obstacles to free competition and state-sanctioned
social policies. The degree of competition in markets and the role of
intervention and regulation as well as the scope of state ownership vary across
different models of capitalism. The extent to which different markets are free
and the rules defining private property are matters of politics and policy.
Most of the existing capitalist economies are mixed economies that combine
elements of free markets with state intervention and in some cases economic
planning
Market economies have existed under many
forms of government and in many different times, places and cultures. Modern
capitalist societies developed in Western Europe in a process that led to the
Industrial Revolution. Capitalist systems with varying degrees of direct
government intervention have since become dominant in the Western world and
continue to spread. Economic growth is a characteristic tendency of capitalist
economies.
CAPITALIST
EXPLOITATION
One feature of this approach taken by Marx (1867, 1990) and
Marxism, from which we retain the necessity of exploitation, under stood as a
relationship of free and legal exchange of objectively asymmetrical magnitudes,
to all stages of capitalism. In opposition to that approach, neoclassical
economics considered exploitation to be a problem of compensation for a factor
of production at below its marginal productivity (Pigou 1920; Flatau 2001). A
liberal theory of exploitation can be found in Steiner (1984), who conceives of
exploitation as situations in which a third party (i.e. the state) limits an
actor's exercise of liberty, making it impossible for this or other actors to
be able to buy or sell a good for the value that another party was willing to
offer. Among other limitations, not that of the actor's freedom but of these
perspectives, is that they only give an account of individual, contingent
situations; another more significant limitation is that according to these
approaches the exploiter could be, for example, a worker who in the face of the
capitalist asserts her techniques in order to demand a wage increase. In that
view, the unionized worker would exploit the capitalist. Other significant
approaches arise from reformulations of the Marxist theory of exploitation
which criticize and abandon the labor theory of value, an idea shared here. In
sociology this is the case for analytical Marxism (Cohen 1979; Roemer 1989;
Elster 1985) and some institutionalist authors (Hodgson 1980) and the Sraffians
in political economy (Garegnani 1979). However, none of these perspectives
sufficiently incorporates the exploitation of knowledge. The explicit idea that
the surplus value the exploiter appropriates (the capitalist exploiter in
particular) could have some relationship with the knowledge carried and put to
use by the exploited, is not adequately discussed. However, in various
investigations into the relationship between knowledge and capitalism time and
again we have empirically found diverse manners by which companies successful
in the accumulation of capital legally take control of those vital knowledges
without paying their value for them (Zukerfeld 2010; 2012; 2016). In these
cases, labor does not lose those knowledges, it continues possessing them, but
capital has copied them and can then dispense with the bearer that the workers
represent.
Having made these superficial references to
the literature, we can now move on to defining capitalist exploitation and its
three varieties. Some features of capitalist exploitation are intrinsic to all
forms of exploitation and have already been discussed. Meanwhile, others will
appear here for the first time. Capitalist exploitation refers to reactions
between human subjects that can be defined by the following characteristics:
1. They occur in the framework of
capitalist productive processes.
2. They generate exchanges that are
objectively asymmetrical in terms of the economic value exchanged between two
types of actors, E (exploiters) and E (exploited).
3. The E actors acquire an objective
surplus value in economic terms in relation to, and at the expense of, the e
actors.
4. The E actors contribute their energies
and different types of knowledge to the productive process, and receive a
compensation approximately equal to (not less than) the value of the expended
energies, but not all (or nothing) of the value of the translated knowledges.
Thus, the essence of capitalist exploitation is the unremunerated knowledge of
the E actors.
5. The E actors, in subjective terms:
5.1 Set in motion the productive processes
with the aim of:
5.1.1 Producing commodities.
5.1.2 Obtaining an economic profit from the
sale of these commodities.
5.2 Have a wide-ranging vision of the
productive process.
6. The e actors, in subjective terms:
6.1 Consent, to a greater or lesser degree,
to the specific exchange they participate in.
6.2 May represent to themselves the
exchanged values as equivalent or otherwise.
6.3
Have a fragmentary, limited, view of the productive process in which they are
incorporated.
7. In terms of inter subjective knowledge:
7.1 Regarding normative knowledge, the
productive processes and exchanges within them take place within the framework
of the law.
7.2 With respect to axiological knowledge,
exploitation takes place framed by ideologies.
There are three types of capitalist
exploitation:
Exploitation through alienation |
Exploitation through reproduction |
Exploitation through other factors |
The energies and the knowledge of the
exploited are translated by objectification in the product of labor whose
ownership is in the hands of the capitalist. |
exploited are translated by codification
(with a possible transitory passage through subjectivity) (in) to different
forms of information whose ownership is in the hands of the capitalist. |
The knowledge administered by the
exploiters, generally digital information, are translated to the subjectivity
or inter subjectivity of the exploited. |
The capitalist obtains labor time (energy
+ knowledge). This time can be inside or
outside the productive unit, but the capitalist appropriates the fruits of
the labor time. |
The capitalist acquires ownership of
certain forms of knowledge (produced over longer or shorter time spans,
within or outside of the working day). |
The capitalist obtains human attention time in order to
inoculate certain knowledge(generally outside of the working day). |
The capitalist pays, usually in monetary
terms, for the cost of the energies necessary for the reproduction of the
worker. |
The capitalist pays in monetary or, more
commonly, in non-monetary terms (such as recognition knowledge). |
The capitalist pays in non-monetary terms
(with access to contents or software, whose monetary cost is lower than that
of attention). |
The commodity (or its intermediary
products) that arises from the productive process
(a good or service) is alienated and erodes with consumption, meaning that
the identical repetition of the productive process requires the subject be
exploited through alienation again. |
The knowledge (subjective or codified as
information) are not alienated (they do not erode with use), so the exploited
subject they have been extracted from is not generally necessary for the
repetition of the same productive process. |
Accumulation of attention, and is
consumed with its productive use. This means that the identical repetition of
the productive process requires the be exploited
through attention again. |
however this is one side of coin!
keep awaiting for our next part on this blog which will come soon!
Credits:
Sahil Lukman
Tadvi
MIS -
112011048
Metallurgy
Note: This blog is meant for educational purposes only. We do not own any Copyrights related to images and information, all the rights go to their respective owners. The sole purpose of this blog is to Educate, Inspire, and Empower and to create awareness in the viewers. The usage is non-commercial (Not for Profit) and we do not make any money from it.
FOLLOW US ON:-
INSTAGRAM :
https://bit.ly/coep_blogs_insta
LINKEDIN:
https://bit.ly/coep_blogs_linkedIn
YOUTUBE:-
https://bit.ly/Coep_blogs_YouTube
Knowledgeable 💯
ReplyDelete